Add To Cart

Section 20
Social Influences on Male Sexuality

Question 20 | Answer Booklet | Table of Contents


The evolutionary approach has more to say about the early social environment than some of its critics may think. As Wright (1994) says, "if we want to know, say, how levels of ambition or of insecurity get adjusted by early experience, we must first ask why natural selection made them adjustable?' The same is true of levels of sexual restraint and of willingness to use violence to obtain desired goals. Although some individual differences in these behaviors may be due to genetic differences (Ellis 1989), "a larger role is played by genetic commonalties: by a generic species-wide developmental program that absorbs information from the social environment and adjusts the maturing mind accordingly" (Wright 1994). Even when a behavior is heritable, an individual's behavior is still a product of development, and thus it has a causal environmental component.

An example involving heritable resistance to an infectious disease should be illustrative. An individual who is genetically predisposed to infection with the disease cannot get it without encountering the infectious agent. And the genes in question may not affect a disease state, even when the individual encounters the agent, if the individual is well nourished and capable of combating the agent.

The evolutionary model views the human brain as a bundle of numerous specialized adaptations created by specific, evolved gene-environment interactions during their ontogeny. After their ontogenetic construction, these adaptations interact with specific aspects of the environment to produce rape.

Essentially all men have sexual psychological adaptations designed for obtaining a large number of mates. However, heritable adjustments in the details of certain sexual adaptations in response to environmental cues processed during development probably create some individual differences in ease of activation of these adaptations. The mechanisms that make such adjustments are facultative-that is, dependent on specific environmental variables. Even if there are significant genetic differences among individual men in some or all of the psychological adaptations that underlie rape, to fully understand rape and to reduce it we will have to determine how environmental differences affect the propensity to rape. The same holds if the psychological adaptations that generate rape reflect multiple sexual adaptations that exist in a mix in the population of men as a result of frequency-dependent selection (as may be true of psychopathic versus non-psychopathic phenotypes, for example).

It is important to realize that "this emphasis on psychological development doesn't leave us back where social scientists were twenty-five years ago, attributing everything they saw to often unspecified 'environmental forces" (Wright 1994, p. 82). Instead, an understanding of the ultimate evolutionary reasons why humans have facultative adaptations that respond to variables in the social environment greatly enhances our ability to specify what social variables influence development in what ways. This also gives the evolutionary approach an advantage over approaches that use arbitrarily chosen environmental factors to explain rape. For example, many proponents of the social science theory of rape (e.g., Denmark and Friedman 1985; Stock 1991) hold that one specific way in which males in some cultures are taught to rape is through the viewing of violent pornography, which inspires imitative behavior. The social scientists pushing this notion, however, cannot explain why the human brain is purportedly structured so as to respond in this specific way to the specific environmental stimulus of violent pornography. Why, for example, should males seek out and imitate violent pornography but not other human activities depicted in videos? There is no consideration of the ultimate basis for the asserted proximate explanation, no sound theoretical foundation for it. Aside from the obvious fact that violent pornography cannot account for the historical and cross-cultural (indeed cross-species) occurrence of rape, such an arbitrary environmental explanation is refuted by everything we know about biases in human development, perception, cognition, emotions, and motivation. It also has a logical flaw: An environmental factor is identified as a cause of a human behavior without any attempt to explain why other kinds of environmental variables that could conceivably also influence the same category of behavior do not do so. Consequently, although the viewing of violent pornography may figure in the proximate causation of the raping behavior of some men, this view is severely limited in its ability to predict anything useful about rape or related behaviors. It cannot explain the data on who is raped, or the data on when and where rape occurs. Although the removal of violent pornography may be desirable in its own right, it is very unlikely to solve the problem of rape.

Rape occurs among humans under a wide range of "physical" and "cultural" environments-indeed, it occurs in all the environments in which humans societies have been known to exist. Hence, cross-cultural evidence actually indicates that a relatively narrow set of environmental changes (including the punishments mentioned in the previous chapter and the structural environmental barriers described below) might be needed to reduce the incidence of rape significantly. The real lesson to be drawn from cross-cultural studies is not that rape will vanish with the end of patriarchy.
Once the scientifically false beliefs that arbitrary learning is all-important in creating human behavior and that rape can be prevented simply by refraining from teaching males to rape are abandoned, they can be replaced with ideas derived from the evolutionary model. Those ideas can then provide direction for efforts to prevent rape by changing the identified aspects of the environment.

We agree with social scientists that males should be educated not to use force or the threat of force to obtain sex. However, we suggest that educational programs aimed at preventing rape would be much more successful if they would focus on the goal that motivates males to use such tactics. In direct contrast to the social science explanation of rape, the clearest implication of evolutionary theory is that the motivation for rape is a result of the differences between male and female sexuality. That is, the evolved psychological adaptations that produce male sexual motivation are necessary proximate causes of rape. It follows that creating environmental conditions that will decrease the frequency of rape requires identification of the exact nature of the psychological mechanisms that guide male sexual behavior. The more we understand how these mechanisms develop and what cues they respond to, the better we will be able to modify male sexual development and associated male sexual behavior.

Not only are ultimate explanations of male sexual motivation ignored by many of those who wish to prevent rape; the potential importance of such knowledge is actively denied by most social scientists and by nearly all academic feminists. For these individuals, the key to preventing rape is convincing men and women that rape is a political act that has nothing to do with biological differences between male and female sexuality Indeed, the idea that rapists are sexually motivated is often considered to be a "rape myth" that must be eradicated by "education?' For example, Fonow et al. (1992, pp. 118-119) suggest that "feminist rape education needs to address the themes of rape as sex and rape as social control" and report that "women's rejection of rape as sex was reinforced and supported through the education; men's beliefs were confronted, but perhaps not forcefully enough?' Syzmanski et al. (1993, pp. 54-55) claim that their "rape awareness workshop appears to have been an effective educational forum" insofar as "subjects who had not attended an awareness workshop thought that sex was a motivation for rape. . . significantly more than did those who had attended the workshop?' According to Stock (1991, p. 73), "for sexual coercion to cease, women must accrue enough power through increased access to concrete resources, expertise, and status to make it less possible for males to continue to maintain constructs and beliefs that stipulate male domination of females?' Repetition of the claim that rape is not motivated by sexual desire is the greatest obstacle to the creation of more effective means of preventing rape.

Rejection of the overwhelming evidence that rapists are sexually motivated appears to be grounded in the belief that rapists driven by lust might not be considered responsible for their actions. Yet, to our knowledge, proponents of the social science model never assert that the supposed male drive to control and dominate women excuses a rapist's behavior, even though that alleged motivation is claimed to be so powerful as to account for nearly all aspects of male-female relations. (Again, scientific explanations of behavior only provide information about the causes of actions;
they imply nothing about who should or should not be held responsible for their actions.)

In reality, the role of sexual motivation as a cause of rape should be a reason for optimism about future attempts to prevent rape. Consider these two points:
o Many men don't rape and are not sexually aroused by laboratory depictions of rape. This suggests that there are cues in the development environments of many men that prohibit raping behavior.
o Acknowledging the role of sexual motivation allows the formidable and rapidly increasing body of scientific knowledge about the evolution of male sexuality to be applied to identifying the cues that prevent rape and to lowering the frequency of rape.

The first step in understanding how the "social environment" (that is, the behavior of other people) influences the ontogeny of male sexuality is to remember the crucial finding from the evidence on non-human species: male sexual pursuit of unwilling females commonly emerges from onto-genies that lack any sexual socialization. That is, rape occurs even when males are not encouraged to rape. In view of this fundamental aspect of male sexuality, it is not surprising that among humans, contrary to much social science writing on gender roles, "the great majority of prescriptive messages concerning [male sexuality, including rape] are intended to suppress it, not to foster it" (Symons 1979, p. 303). Indeed, any explanation of the species-typical sexual behavior of human males must be able to account for the universal presence of "moral traditions" that "limit male performing sexual acts under certain conditions" (LeVine 1977, p. 222).
- Thornhill PhD, Randy and Craig T. Palmer, A Natural History of Rape: Biological Bases of Sexual Coercion; The MIT Press: Massachusetts, 2000

Personal Reflection Exercise #6
The preceding section contained information about social influences on male sexuality. Write three case study examples regarding how you might use the content of this section in your practice.

QUESTION 20
What is the first step in understanding how the "social environment" influences the ontogeny of male sexuality? To select and enter your answer go to Answer Booklet
.


Answer Booklet
Section 21
Table of Contents
Top