![]() Healthcare Training Institute - Quality Education since 1979 CE for Psychologist, Social Worker, Counselor, & MFT!!
Section 20 Question 20 | Answer Booklet | Table of Contents
An example involving heritable resistance to an infectious disease should be illustrative. An individual who is genetically predisposed to infection with the disease cannot get it without encountering the infectious agent. And the genes in question may not affect a disease state, even when the individual encounters the agent, if the individual is well nourished and capable of combating the agent. The evolutionary model views the human brain as a bundle of numerous specialized adaptations created by specific, evolved gene-environment interactions during their ontogeny. After their ontogenetic construction, these adaptations interact with specific aspects of the environment to produce rape. Essentially all men have sexual psychological adaptations designed for obtaining a large number of mates. However, heritable adjustments in the details of certain sexual adaptations in response to environmental cues processed during development probably create some individual differences in ease of activation of these adaptations. The mechanisms that make such adjustments are facultative-that is, dependent on specific environmental variables. Even if there are significant genetic differences among individual men in some or all of the psychological adaptations that underlie rape, to fully understand rape and to reduce it we will have to determine how environmental differences affect the propensity to rape. The same holds if the psychological adaptations that generate rape reflect multiple sexual adaptations that exist in a mix in the population of men as a result of frequency-dependent selection (as may be true of psychopathic versus non-psychopathic phenotypes, for example). It is important to realize that "this emphasis on psychological development doesn't leave us back where social scientists were twenty-five years ago, attributing everything they saw to often unspecified 'environmental forces" (Wright 1994, p. 82). Instead, an understanding of the ultimate evolutionary reasons why humans have facultative adaptations that respond to variables in the social environment greatly enhances our ability to specify what social variables influence development in what ways. This also gives the evolutionary approach an advantage over approaches that use arbitrarily chosen environmental factors to explain rape. For example, many proponents of the social science theory of rape (e.g., Denmark and Friedman 1985; Stock 1991) hold that one specific way in which males in some cultures are taught to rape is through the viewing of violent pornography, which inspires imitative behavior. The social scientists pushing this notion, however, cannot explain why the human brain is purportedly structured so as to respond in this specific way to the specific environmental stimulus of violent pornography. Why, for example, should males seek out and imitate violent pornography but not other human activities depicted in videos? There is no consideration of the ultimate basis for the asserted proximate explanation, no sound theoretical foundation for it. Aside from the obvious fact that violent pornography cannot account for the historical and cross-cultural (indeed cross-species) occurrence of rape, such an arbitrary environmental explanation is refuted by everything we know about biases in human development, perception, cognition, emotions, and motivation. It also has a logical flaw: An environmental factor is identified as a cause of a human behavior without any attempt to explain why other kinds of environmental variables that could conceivably also influence the same category of behavior do not do so. Consequently, although the viewing of violent pornography may figure in the proximate causation of the raping behavior of some men, this view is severely limited in its ability to predict anything useful about rape or related behaviors. It cannot explain the data on who is raped, or the data on when and where rape occurs. Although the removal of violent pornography may be desirable in its own right, it is very unlikely to solve the problem of rape. Rape occurs among humans under a wide range of "physical"
and "cultural" environments-indeed, it occurs in all the environments
in which humans societies have been known to exist. Hence, cross-cultural evidence
actually indicates that a relatively narrow set of environmental changes (including
the punishments mentioned in the previous chapter and the structural environmental
barriers described below) might be needed to reduce the incidence of rape significantly.
The real lesson to be drawn from cross-cultural studies is not that rape will
vanish with the end of patriarchy. We agree with social scientists that males should be educated not to use force or the threat of force to obtain sex. However, we suggest that educational programs aimed at preventing rape would be much more successful if they would focus on the goal that motivates males to use such tactics. In direct contrast to the social science explanation of rape, the clearest implication of evolutionary theory is that the motivation for rape is a result of the differences between male and female sexuality. That is, the evolved psychological adaptations that produce male sexual motivation are necessary proximate causes of rape. It follows that creating environmental conditions that will decrease the frequency of rape requires identification of the exact nature of the psychological mechanisms that guide male sexual behavior. The more we understand how these mechanisms develop and what cues they respond to, the better we will be able to modify male sexual development and associated male sexual behavior. Not only are ultimate explanations of male sexual motivation ignored by many of those who wish to prevent rape; the potential importance of such knowledge is actively denied by most social scientists and by nearly all academic feminists. For these individuals, the key to preventing rape is convincing men and women that rape is a political act that has nothing to do with biological differences between male and female sexuality Indeed, the idea that rapists are sexually motivated is often considered to be a "rape myth" that must be eradicated by "education?' For example, Fonow et al. (1992, pp. 118-119) suggest that "feminist rape education needs to address the themes of rape as sex and rape as social control" and report that "women's rejection of rape as sex was reinforced and supported through the education; men's beliefs were confronted, but perhaps not forcefully enough?' Syzmanski et al. (1993, pp. 54-55) claim that their "rape awareness workshop appears to have been an effective educational forum" insofar as "subjects who had not attended an awareness workshop thought that sex was a motivation for rape. . . significantly more than did those who had attended the workshop?' According to Stock (1991, p. 73), "for sexual coercion to cease, women must accrue enough power through increased access to concrete resources, expertise, and status to make it less possible for males to continue to maintain constructs and beliefs that stipulate male domination of females?' Repetition of the claim that rape is not motivated by sexual desire is the greatest obstacle to the creation of more effective means of preventing rape. Rejection
of the overwhelming evidence that rapists are sexually motivated appears to be
grounded in the belief that rapists driven by lust might not be considered responsible
for their actions. Yet, to our knowledge, proponents of the social science model
never assert that the supposed male drive to control and dominate women excuses
a rapist's behavior, even though that alleged motivation is claimed to be so powerful
as to account for nearly all aspects of male-female relations. (Again, scientific
explanations of behavior only provide information about the causes of actions; In reality, the role of sexual motivation as a
cause of rape should be a reason for optimism about future attempts to prevent
rape. Consider these two points: The
first step in understanding how the "social environment" (that is, the
behavior of other people) influences the ontogeny of male sexuality is to remember
the crucial finding from the evidence on non-human species: male sexual pursuit
of unwilling females commonly emerges from onto-genies that lack any sexual socialization.
That is, rape occurs even when males are not encouraged to rape. In view of this
fundamental aspect of male sexuality, it is not surprising that among humans,
contrary to much social science writing on gender roles, "the great majority
of prescriptive messages concerning [male sexuality, including rape] are intended
to suppress it, not to foster it" (Symons 1979, p. 303). Indeed, any explanation
of the species-typical sexual behavior of human males must be able to account
for the universal presence of "moral traditions" that "limit male
performing sexual acts under certain conditions" (LeVine 1977, p. 222). Personal
Reflection Exercise #6 QUESTION
20 |